Martin Escardo 29 April 2014. A proposition-indexed product of pointed compact sets is itself compact. But the assumption that a proposition-indexed product of compact sets is compact gives weak excluded middle (negative propositions are decidable). The definition of compactness-pointedness (or exhaustive searchability) is compact∙ X = (p : X → 𝟚) → Σ x₀ ꞉ X , p x₀ = ₁ → (x : X) → p x = ₁ We refer to such an x₀ as a universal witness. With excluded middle for propositions, the above claim is not surprising, because (𝟘 → Y) = Y^𝟘 ≃ 𝟙 (which is always compact), (𝟙 → Y) = Y^𝟙 ≃ Y (which is compact if Y is), and excluded middle for a proposition X amounts to X = 𝟘 or X = 𝟙, so that Y^X is compact∙ if Y is compact∙ and X is a proposition. The point is that (1) We can reach this conclusion without excluded middle. (2) This also holds for dependent products: Π x : X , Y x is compact∙ if X is a proposition and Y x is compact∙ for every x : X. (This product is also written (x : X) → Y x or Π Y in Agda.) \begin{code} {-# OPTIONS --safe --without-K #-} open import MLTT.Spartan module TypeTopology.PropTychonoff where open import MLTT.Two-Properties open import TypeTopology.CompactTypes open import UF.Equiv open import UF.FunExt open import UF.PropIndexedPiSigma open import UF.Subsingletons prop-tychonoff : funext 𝓤 𝓥 → {X : 𝓤 ̇ } {Y : X → 𝓥 ̇ } → is-prop X → ((x : X) → is-compact∙ (Y x)) → is-compact∙ (Π Y) prop-tychonoff {𝓤} {𝓥} fe {X} {Y} X-is-prop ε p = γ where have-ε : (x : X) → is-compact∙ (Y x) have-ε = ε have-p : Π Y → 𝟚 have-p = p 𝕗 : (x : X) → Π Y ≃ Y x 𝕗 = prop-indexed-product fe X-is-prop \end{code} The essence of the first part of the proof is this: \begin{code} crude : X → is-compact∙ (Π Y) crude x = compact∙-types-are-closed-under-equiv (≃-sym (𝕗 x)) (ε x) \end{code} But this is very crude for our purposes (or so it seems). So we instead proceed as follows. We first introduct some abbreviations. \begin{code} f : (x : X) → Π Y → Y x f x = ⌜ 𝕗 x ⌝ f-explicitly : (x : X) (φ : Π Y) → f x φ = φ x f-explicitly x φ = refl f⁻¹ : (x : X) → Y x → Π Y f⁻¹ x = ⌜ 𝕗 x ⌝⁻¹ \end{code} We define a predicate q x : Y x → 𝟚, for each x : X, from the predicate p : Π Y → 𝟚 via the above equivalence: \begin{code} q : (x : X) → Y x → 𝟚 q x y = p (f⁻¹ x y) \end{code} We argue that the following is a universal witness for the searchability of the type Π Y w.r.t. the predicate p: \begin{code} φ₀ : Π Y φ₀ x = universal-witness (ε x) (q x) \end{code} By hypothesis, it satisfies: \begin{code} φ₀-universality : (x : X) → q x (φ₀ x) = ₁ → (y : Y x) → q x y = ₁ φ₀-universality x = witness-universality (ε x) (q x) \end{code} By expanding the definitions, this amounts to: \begin{code} φ₀-universality₀ : (x : X) → p (f⁻¹ x (φ₀ x)) = ₁ → (y : Y x) → p (f⁻¹ x y) = ₁ φ₀-universality₀ = φ₀-universality \end{code} Because f x φ = φ x, the above amounts to the following: \begin{code} φ₀-universality₁ : (x : X) → p (f⁻¹ x (f x φ₀)) = ₁ → (y : Y x) → p (f⁻¹ x y) = ₁ φ₀-universality₁ = φ₀-universality₀ \end{code} In particular, choosing y = f x φ, we get: \begin{code} φ₀-universality₁-particular-case : (x : X) → p (f⁻¹ x (f x φ₀)) = ₁ → (φ : Π Y) → p (f⁻¹ x (f x φ)) = ₁ φ₀-universality₁-particular-case x r φ = φ₀-universality₁ x r (f x φ) \end{code} This in turn gives \begin{code} φ₀-is-universal-witness-assuming-X : X → p φ₀ = ₁ → (φ : Π Y) → p φ = ₁ φ₀-is-universal-witness-assuming-X x r φ = p φ =⟨ ap p ((inverses-are-retractions' (𝕗 x) φ)⁻¹) ⟩ p (f⁻¹ x (f x φ)) =⟨ φ₀-universality₁-particular-case x s φ ⟩ ₁ ∎ where s = p (f⁻¹ x (f x φ₀)) =⟨ ap p (inverses-are-retractions' (𝕗 x) φ₀) ⟩ p φ₀ =⟨ r ⟩ ₁ ∎ \end{code} Notice that the point x : X vanishes from the conclusion, and so we are able to omit it from the hypothesis, which is crucial for what follows. We get the same conclusion if X is empty: \begin{code} φ₀-is-universal-witness-assuming-X-empty : (X → 𝟘) → p φ₀ = ₁ → (φ : Π Y) → p φ = ₁ φ₀-is-universal-witness-assuming-X-empty u r φ = p φ =⟨ ap p (dfunext fe (λ x → unique-from-𝟘 (u x))) ⟩ p φ₀ =⟨ r ⟩ ₁ ∎ \end{code} So we would get what we want if we had excluded middle, because X is a proposition and the above shows that both X and X → 𝟘 give the desired conclusion that φ₀ is a universal witness. But excluded middle is not needed. We shuffle the arguments of φ₀-is-universal-witness-assuming-X: \begin{code} claim₀ : p φ₀ = ₁ → (φ : Π Y) → X → p φ = ₁ claim₀ r φ x = φ₀-is-universal-witness-assuming-X x r φ \end{code} We then take the contrapositive of the conclusion X → p φ = ₁, and use the fact that if a point of the two-point type 𝟚 is ₀, then it is not ₁: \begin{code} Claim₁ : p φ₀ = ₁ → (φ : Π Y) → p φ = ₀ → (X → 𝟘) Claim₁ r φ = contrapositive (claim₀ r φ) ∘ equal-₀-different-from-₁ \end{code} This concludes the first part of the argument. We now shuffle the arguments of φ₀-is-universal-witness-assuming-X-empty: \begin{code} Claim₂ : p φ₀ = ₁ → (φ : Π Y) → (X → 𝟘) → p φ = ₁ Claim₂ r φ u = φ₀-is-universal-witness-assuming-X-empty u r φ \end{code} Combining the two last claims, we get: \begin{code} Claim₃ : p φ₀ = ₁ → (φ : Π Y) → p φ = ₀ → p φ = ₁ Claim₃ r φ = Claim₂ r φ ∘ Claim₁ r φ \end{code} Finally, we do case analysis on the value of p φ: \begin{code} φ₀-is-universal-witness : p φ₀ = ₁ → (φ : Π Y) → p φ = ₁ φ₀-is-universal-witness r φ = 𝟚-equality-cases (Claim₃ r φ) id \end{code} And we are done: \begin{code} γ : Σ φ₀ ꞉ Π Y , (p φ₀ = ₁ → (φ : Π Y) → p φ = ₁) γ = φ₀ , φ₀-is-universal-witness \end{code} TODO. 9 Sep 2015. We can generalize from X being a subsingleton (or proposition) to X being subfinite (embedded into a finite type). A particular case is the following: \begin{code} prop-tychonoff-corollary : funext 𝓤 𝓥 → {X : 𝓤 ̇ } {Y : 𝓥 ̇ } → is-prop X → is-compact∙ Y → is-compact∙ (X → Y) prop-tychonoff-corollary fe X-is-prop ε = prop-tychonoff fe X-is-prop (λ x → ε) \end{code} This holds even for undecided X (such as X = LPO), or when we have no idea whether X or (X → 𝟘), and hence whether (X → Y) is 𝟙 or Y (or none, if this is undecided)! Better (9 Sep 2015): \begin{code} prop-tychonoff-corollary' : funext 𝓤 𝓥 → {X : 𝓤 ̇ } {Y : 𝓥 ̇ } → is-prop X → (X → is-compact∙ Y) → is-compact∙ (X → Y) prop-tychonoff-corollary' fe = prop-tychonoff fe \end{code} So the function type (LPO → ℕ) is compact! (See the module LPO for a proof.) The Tychonoff theorem for prop-indexed products of compact types doesn't hold. To see this, first notice that a proposition is compact iff it is decidable. Now, the empty type 𝟘 is compact (but not compact∙), and if 𝟘^P, that is, ¬P, where compact for a proposition P, this would imply that ¬P is decidable for every proposition P, which is weak excluded middle, which is not provable. \begin{code} open import UF.ClassicalLogic compact-prop-tychonoff-gives-WEM' : ((X : 𝓤 ̇ ) (Y : X → 𝓥 ̇ ) → is-prop X → ((x : X) → is-compact (Y x)) → is-compact (Π Y)) → WEM' 𝓤 compact-prop-tychonoff-gives-WEM' {𝓤} {𝓥} τ X X-is-prop = δ γ where Y : X → 𝓥 ̇ Y x = 𝟘 negation-compact : is-compact (X → 𝟘 {𝓥}) negation-compact = τ X Y X-is-prop (λ p → 𝟘-compact) γ : is-decidable (X → 𝟘 {𝓥}) γ = compact-types-are-decidable (X → 𝟘) negation-compact δ : is-decidable (X → 𝟘 {𝓥}) → is-decidable (¬ X) δ (inl f) = inl (𝟘-elim ∘ f) δ (inr ϕ) = inr (contrapositive (λ f → 𝟘-elim ∘ f) ϕ) \end{code} If we further assume function extensionality, we get WEM from WEM', and hence we can replace the conclusion of the above fact by WEM.